The Ninth National Congress of the Italian
Society of the Science of Anesthetics, held at Rome on 15th-17th
October, 1956, submitted three questions to Us, through the
President of the Organizing Committee, Professor Piero Mazzoni
—questions which deal with the religious and moral implications of
pain prevention in the light of the Natural Law, and especially of
Christian doctrine as contained in the Gospel and taught by the
Church.
THREE RELIGIOUS AND MORAL QUESTIONS CONCERNING PAIN PREVENTION
(ANALGESIA)
These questions, of unquestionable interest, do not fail to
awaken intellectual and emotional reactions in men today. Among
Christians especially, there is evidence of many and various
trends. Some approve unreservedly of the practice of analgesia;
others would be inclined to reject it outright as contradictory to
the ideal of Christian heroism. Others without the least sacrifice
of that ideal, are ready to take their stand midway. That is why
We are being asked to voice Our thoughts on the three following
points:
-
Is there a universal moral obligation to refuse analgesia
and to accept physical pain in a spirit of faith?
-
Is it in accord with the spirit of the Gospel to bring
about, by means of drugs, the loss of consciousness and of the
use of a man’s higher faculties?
-
Is it lawful for the dying or those in danger of death to
make use of drugs if there exist medical reasons for their use?
Can one use drugs even if the lessening of pain is probably
accompanied by a shortening of life?…
QUESTION 1: ON THE GENERAL MORAL OBLIGATION TO ENDURE PHYSICAL
PAIN
In the first place, then, you ask whether there is a general
moral obligation to endure physical pain. In order to give a more
precise answer to your question, We shall treat of various aspects
of the matter. And first, it is evident that in certain cases the
acceptance of physical suffering is a matter of serious
obligation. Thus a man is bound in conscience to accept suffering
whenever he is faced with the inescapable alternative of enduring
suffering or of acting contrary to a moral obligation, either by
positive action or by omission. The martyrs could not avoid either
torture or death without denying their faith or without avoiding
the serious obligation of bearing witness to it when the occasion
was given. But it is not necessary to go back to the martyrs. At
the present time there are found magnificent examples of
Christians who, for weeks, months, and even for years, endure
suffering and physical violence in order to remain faithful to God
and to their conscience.
Free Acceptance and the Desire of Suffering
Your question, however, does not refer to this situation; it
has in mind rather the free acceptance and the desire of suffering
in itself and for itself. To recall at once a definite example of
this, We refer to the Address We gave on Jan. 8, 1956, with
reference to new methods of painless childbirth. There it was
asked whether, by virtue of the text in Scripture: "In sorrow
shalt thou bring forth children," the mother was obliged to
accept all the sufferings and to refuse relief from pain by either
natural or artificial means. We answer that there was no
obligation of this kind. Man, even after the fall, retains the
right of control over the forces of nature, of employing them for
his own use, and consequently of deriving benefit from all the
resources which it offers him either to suppress or to avoid
physical pain. We added that, for the Christian, suffering is not
something purely negative, but on the contrary, is linked with
lofty religious and moral values, and hence can be desired and
sought even if no moral obligation to do so exists in a particular
case. Continuing, We said:
The life and sufferings of Our Lord, the pains which so many
great men have endured and even sought, and by reason of which
they grew to maturity and rose to the highest point of Christian
heroism, the daily examples which We have before Our eyes of the
acceptance of the Cross with resignation —all this reveals the
meaning of suffering, of patient acceptance of pain in the
present working out of salvation during the period of this
earthly life.
The Duty of Renunciation and Interior Purification
Moreover, the Christian is bound to mortify his flesh and to
strive after his interior purification, for it is impossible, in
the long run, to avoid sin and to carry out all one’s duties
faithfully, if this effort at mortification and purification be
neglected. Physical suffering becomes a necessity and must be
accepted to the extent that, without its aid, mastery over self
and disorderly tendencies is unattainable; but in so far as it is
not required for this purpose, one cannot assert that there exists
a strict obligation in the matter. The Christian, then, is never
obliged to will suffering for its own sake: he considers it,
according to circumstances, as a means more or less suited to the
end which he is pursuing.
Invitation to a Higher Perfection
One can consider what is of strict obligation; but it is also
possible to look at the demands of the Christian faith, the
invitation to a higher perfection, which is not imposed under pain
of sin. Is the Christian obliged to accept physical pain so as not
to set himself in contradiction to the ideal which his Faith
proposes to him? Does not a refusal in this matter imply a lack of
the spirit of faith?
That the Christian experiences this desire to accept, and even
to seek, physical pain in order the better to share in the Passion
of Christ, to renounce the world and the pleasures of the senses,
and to mortify his own flesh, is beyond dispute; but, at the same
time, it is important to give a correct interpretation of this
tendency. Those who manifest it exteriorly do not necessarily
possess genuine Christian heroism; but it would also be a mistake
to declare that those who do not manifest it are quite devoid of
it. This heroism can, in fact, reveal itself in many other ways.
Take, for example, a Christian who carries out, day after day,
from morning till night, all the duties of his state or
profession, the laws of God and of men: one who prays with
recollection, does his work wholeheartedly, resists his evil
passions, shows his neighbor the charity and service that is his
due; endures bravely, without murmuring, whatever God sends him:
that man is always living beneath the sign of the Cross of Christ
whether physical suffering is present or not, whether he endures
it or avoids it by means which are lawful. Even if one considers
only obligations binding a man under pain of sin, he cannot live
or carry out his daily work as a Christian without being ever
ready for sacrifice and, one may say, without constantly
sacrificing himself. The acceptance of suffering is only one way,
among many others, of indicating what is the real essential: the
will to love God and to serve Him in all things. It is, above all,
in the perfection of this voluntary disposition that the quality
of the Christian life and its heroism consists.
Motives Which Allow the Avoidance of Physical Pain
In specific cases, which are the motives which allow avoidance
of physical pain without involving any conflict with a serious
obligation or with the ideal of the Christian life? One could list
quite a number: but, in spite of their variety, they are finally
summed up in the fact that, in the long run, the pain is
preventing the obtaining of some good or advantage of higher
worth. It is possible that suffering may be preferable for a
particular person in a definite situation; but, in general, the
harm caused forces men to protect themselves against it. Beyond
doubt, suffering will never be completely banished from among men,
but its harmful effects can be kept within narrower limits. And
so, just as one masters a natural force to draw advantage from it,
the Christian makes use of suffering as a spur to his effort to
mount higher and purify himself in the spiritual life, in order to
carry out his duties better and answer the call to a higher
perfection.
In keeping with the abilities or dispositions above-mentioned,
it is for each one to adopt solutions suited to his own case,
without at the same time hindering other advantages and other
greater benefits. The value of each solution will be measured
according as it is a means of progress in the interior life, of
more perfect mortification, of more faithful accomplishment of the
individual’s duty, of greater readiness to follow the prompting of
grace. In order to be sure that such is really the case, a man
will look to the rules of Christian prudence and the advice of an
experienced spiritual director.
Conclusions and Answer to the First Question
From these replies, you will easily draw useful directives for
practical application.
The fundamental principles of the technique of anaesthesia, a
science as well as an art, and the end pursued, give rise to no
difficulties. It combats those forces which, in a great many
respects, produce harmful effects and hinder a greater good.
The doctor who accepts its methods is in no way acting against
the natural moral order nor against the specifically Christian
idea. He is seeking, in accord with the ordinance of the Creator,
to bring suffering under man’s control, and to do so he makes use
of the conquests of science and of technical skill in keeping with
the principles We have set forth and which will guide his
decisions in particular cases.
The patient desirous of avoiding or of soothing the pain, can,
without disquiet of conscience, make use of the means discovered
by science and which, in themselves, are not immoral. Particular
circumstances can impose another line of conduct, but the
Christian’s duty of renunciation and of interior purification is
not an obstacle to the use of anesthetics, because it is possible
to fulfill that duty in another manner. The same rule applies also
to the demands of the Christian ideal which go beyond the call of
duty.
QUESTION 2: THE STATE OF INSENSIBILITY (NARCOSIS) AND THE
TOTAL OR PARTIAL DEPRIVATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Your second question concerned the state of insensibility and
the total or partial deprivation of consciousness in the light of
Christian morals. You expressed it thus:
The complete abolition of sense perception in all its forms
(general anesthesia), or the diminution to a greater or less
extent of the perception of pain (partial anesthesia and
analgesia), is always accompanied in the one case by
disappearance, in the other by the lessening, of consciousness and
of the highest intellectual faculties (memory, process of
association, critical faculties, etc.). Are these phenomena, which
enter into the normal framework of insensibility during surgical
operations, and of the analgesic practice, before and after an
operation–are they compatible with the spirit of the Gospel?
The Gospel tells us that, immediately before the Crucifixion,
Our Lord was offered some wine mixed with gall, doubtless to
mitigate His sufferings. After having tasted it, He would not
drink it, because He wished to suffer fully conscious, thus
fulfilling what He had said to Peter at the time of the arrest:
"The chalice which My Father has given Me, shall I not drink it?"
So bitter was this chalice, that Jesus had pleaded in the agony of
His soul: "Father, let this chalice pass from Me! But not as I
will but as Thou wilt!" Does the attitude of Christ towards
His Passion, as revealed in this and other passages of the Gospel,
permit the Christian to accept the total or partial state of
insensibility?
Since you arc considering the question under two aspects, We
shall examine successively the suppression of the pain, then the
lessening or the total suppression of consciousness and of the use
of the higher faculties.
Disappearance of Pain
The disappearance of pain depends, as you say, either on the
suppression of general sense-perception (general anesthesia), or
on the lowering, more or less noticeable, of the capacity for
suffering (partial anesthesia and analgesia). We have already
stated the essential point on the moral aspect of suppression of
pain. It is of little consequence, from the religious and moral
point of view, whether it be caused by a state of insensibility or
by other means; within the limits indicated, it gives rise to no
objection and remains in accord with the spirit of the Gospel.
However, one must neither deny nor underestimate the fact that the
acceptance of physical suffering (whether obligatory or not), even
on the occasions of surgical operations, can reveal a lofty
heroism and frequently gives genuine testimony to a heroic
imitation of the Passion of Christ. Nevertheless, that does not
mean that it is an indispensable part of it; in major operations,
especially, it is not unusual for anesthetics to be essential for
other reasons, and the surgeon or the patient could not omit them
without a lack of Christian prudence. The same holds good for
analgesic practice before and after the operation.
Suppression or Lessening of Consciousness and of the Use of the
Higher Faculties
You then speak of the diminution or suppression of
consciousness, of the use of the higher faculties, as of phenomena
which accompany the loss of sense-perception. Ordinarily, what you
wish to obtain is precisely, this loss of sense-perception; but
often it is impossible to produce it without bringing about at the
same time total or partial loss of consciousness. Outside the
sphere of surgery, this process is often reversed, not only in
medicine, but also in psychology and in criminal investigations.
Here it is claimed that a lowering of consciousness is brought
about, and, through it, of the higher faculties, in such a way as
to paralyze the psychic control mechanisms which a man constantly
makes use of for self-mastery and self-direction. He then gives
himself over without any resistance to the play of association of
ideas, and of feelings of volitionary impulses. The dangers of
such a situation are evident; he can even reach the point where he
sets free instinctive urges which are immoral.
These manifestations at the second level of the state of
unconsciousness are well known, and, in practice, one tries to
avert them by means of drugs previously administered. The stopping
of the mechanism of control is declared to be particularly
dangerous when it evokes the revelation of secrets of private or
social life, affecting the person or the family. It is not enough
that the surgeon and his assistants are all bound not only by the
natural secret (secretum naturale), but also by the
professional secret (secretum officiale, secretum commissum)
with respect to all that takes place in the operating-theatre.
There are certain secrets which ought not to be revealed to
anyone, not even, as the technical formula says, "uni viro
prudenti et silentii tenaci." We have already underlined this
in Our Address of 15th April, 1953, on clinical psychology and
psychoanalysis. Hence one can only approve of the use of drugs in
the treatment before the operation in order to avoid these
disadvantages.
Let Us note first of all that in sleep, nature itself
interrupts more or less completely intellectual activity. If,
during light sleep, the use of reason ("usus rationis")
is not entirely abolished, and the individual is still able to
enjoy the use of his higher faculties, as St. Thomas had already
noted, sleep nevertheless excludes the "dominium rationis,"
that power in virtue of which reason freely commands human
activity. It does not follow that if a man gives way to sleep, he
is acting contrary to the moral order in depriving himself of
consciousness and mastery over himself through the use of his
higher faculties. Yet it is also certain that there may be cases
(and it often happens) in which a man cannot permit himself sleep,
but must remain in possession of his higher faculties in order to
perform a moral duty which is obligatory. Sometimes, without being
bound by a strict duty, a man deprives himself of sleep so as to
render services of his free choice, or to impose some self-denial
for the sake of higher moral interests.
The suppression of consciousness, then, by natural sleep, does
not, of itself, raise any difficulty; but it is not lawful to
accept it when it impedes the carrying out of a moral duty. The
giving up of natural sleep can also, in the moral order, be an
expression and a realization of a voluntary striving towards moral
perfection.
Hypnosis
But consciousness can also be reduced by artificial means. It
makes no difference from the moral standpoint whether this result
is obtained by the administration of drugs or by artificially
produced sleep (hypnosis) —which can be called a form of psychic
pain prevention. However, hypnosis, even considered exclusively in
itself, is subject to certain rules. May We recall a brief
reference We made to the medical use of hypnosis, at the beginning
of the Address of 8th January, 1956, on natural painless
childbirth?
In the matter which engages Us at present, there is question of
hypnosis practiced by the doctor to serve a clinical purpose,
while he observes the precautions which science and medical ethics
demand from the doctor as much as from the patient who submits to
it. The moral judgment which We are going to state on the
suppression of consciousness applies to this specific use of
hypnosis.
But We do not wish what We say of hypnosis in the service of
medicine to be extended to hypnosis in general without
qualification. In fact, hypnosis, in so far as it is an object of
scientific research, cannot be studied by any casual individual,
but only by a serious scholar, and within the moral limits valid
for all scientific activity. It is not the affair of some group of
layman or ecclesiastics, who might dabble in it as in some
interesting topic for the sake of mere experience, or even as a
simple hobby.
The Lawfulness of the Suppression or Lessening of Consciousness
To appreciate the lawfulness of the suppression or lessening of
consciousness, one must consider that reasonable and freely
controlled activity is the characteristic mark of the human being.
The individual will be unable to carry out, for example, his daily
work if he remains habitually plunged in a twilight state.
Moreover, he has an obligation to relate all his actions according
to the demands of the moral order. Since the natural energies and
the blind instincts, left to themselves, are incapable of
guaranteeing a regulated activity, it follows that the use of the
reason and of the higher faculties is indispensable both for
seeing clearly the precise terms of the obligation, and for
applying them to particular cases. Hence derives the moral
obligation of not depriving oneself of this consciousness without
true necessity.
It follows that one may not confuse consciousness, or suppress
it, with the sole object of gaining pleasurable sensations, by
indulging in drunkenness and injecting poisons intended to secure
this state, even if one is seeking only a pleasant state of
well-being. Beyond a certain dose, these poisons cause a
disturbance, more or less pronounced, of consciousness and even
its complete darkening. Facts show that the abuse of drugs leads
to the complete neglect of the most fundamental demands of
personal and family life. It is, therefore, entirely reasonable
for the public authorities to intervene to regulate the sale and
the use of these drugs, so as to remove from society serious
physical and moral harm.
Is surgery, in practice, compelled to produce a lessening or
even a complete suppression of consciousness by means of the state
of insensibility (narcosis)? From a technical point of view, the
answer to this question lies within your competence. From the
moral point of view, the principles previously stated in answer to
your first question apply substantially to the state of
insensibility as much as to the suppression of pain. In fact, what
matters to the surgeon in the first place is the suppression of
painful sense-perception, and not that of consciousness. When the
latter remains fully awake, the violent and painful
sense-experiences easily arouse reflexes and reactions which are
often involuntary, but capable of bringing undesirable
complications in their train and even terminating in a fatal
collapse of the heart. To preserve the psychical and organic
balance, to prevent its being violently disturbed, is an important
objective for both doctor and patient; and the state of
insensibility alone allows them to obtain it. It is hardly
necessary to draw attention to the fact that, if one suspected
that others might interfere in an immoral manner while the sick
person is unconscious, this state of induced insensibility would
evoke serious difficulties which would be calling for adequate
safeguards.
The Teaching of the Gospel
To these rules of natural morals, does the Gospel add details
and further demands? If Our Lord on Calvary refused the wine mixed
with gall because He wished to drink to the dregs in full
consciousness the chalice which His Father offered Him, it follows
that man ought to accept and drink the chalice of suffering
whenever God wills it. One need not, however, believe that every
time an occasion to endure pain presents itself, God wills it,
whatever be the conditions and circumstances. The words of the
Gospel and the attitude of Our Lord do not indicate that that is
God’s will for all men and at every moment, and the Church has in
no way given this interpretation to them. Yet the actions and
suggestions of Our Lord hold a deep meaning for all men. In this
world there are countless people who are weighed down by
sufferings (sickness, accidents, wars, natural disasters) to the
bitterness of which they can bring no solace. The example of
Christ on Calvary, His refusal to give relief to His pain, are for
them a source of consolation and strength.
Besides, Our Savior has warned His followers that this chalice
awaits all. The Apostles, and after them the martyrs in their
thousands, have borne witness to it, and do not cease to bear
glorious testimony to it down to the present day. Often, however,
the acceptance of unrelieved suffering involves no obligation and
corresponds to no rule of perfection. The case occurs quite
regularly when serious reasons for this decision exist and the
circumstances do not impose the contrary. It is then possible to
avoid the pain without putting oneself in opposition to the
teaching of the Gospel.
Conclusion and Answer to the Second Question
The conclusion, then, of the exposition of the matter up to
this point can be stated thus: within the limits laid down, and
provided one observes the required conditions, the state of
insensibility involving a lessening or a suppression of
consciousness is permitted by natural morality, and is in keeping
with the spirit of the Gospel
QUESTION 3: ON THE USE OF PAIN-RELIEVING TREATMENTS OF THOSE
WHO ARE DYING
We have now to examine your third question:
Is it permitted in general, and during the period after an
operation in particular, to use analgesic treatments (the
employment of which invariably dulls consciousness), even in the
case of the dying and of patients in danger of death, when there
is a medical reason for this use? Is this permitted even in
certain cases (inoperable cancers and incurable diseases) where
the lessening of the unbearable pain is achieved probably at the
cost of the duration of life, which is thereby shortened?
This third question is fundamentally only an application of the
two preceding to the special case of the dying, and to the
particular effect of a shortening of life.
To declare that the dying have a greater moral obligation than
others —whether from Natural Law or from Christian teaching —to
accept suffering or to refuse its alleviation, is in keeping
neither with the nature of things, nor with the sources of
Revelation, just as, in accord with the spirit of the Gospel,
suffering helps towards the expiation of personal sins and the
gaining of richer merit, those whose life is in danger have
certainly a special motive for accepting it, for, with death quite
near, this possibility of gaining new merits is likely soon to
disappear. This motive, however, directly concerns the sick
person, not the doctor who is engaged in relieving the pain —for
We are supposing that the sick person is assenting to this relief
or has even expressly asked for it. It would clearly be unlawful
to make use of anesthetics against the expressed will of the dying
person (when he is sui iuris).
Some clarification would seem to be needed then, for it is not
uncommon for the explanation to be presented in the wrong manner.
Attempts are sometimes made to prove that the sick and the dying
are obliged to endure physical sufferings in order to acquire more
merits; the reason adduced is the invitation to perfection which
Our Lord addressed to all: "Be ye perfect as your heavenly
Father is perfect," or the words of the Apostle: "This is the will
of God, your sanctification." Sometimes an argument based on
reason is put forward. According to this, no indifference would be
permissible with respect to the obtaining (though gradual and
stage by stage) of the final end towards which man is moving; or,
again, the precept of well-ordered self-love which would insist on
one’s seeking advantages for eternity in the measure in which the
circumstances of daily life permit their attainment; or, even the
first and greatest commandment, of the love of God above all
things, which would allow no choice in profiting by the particular
occasions offered by Providence.
Now, the growth in the love of God and in abandonment to His
will does not come from the sufferings themselves which are
accepted, but from the intention in the will, supported by grace.
This intention, in many of the dying, can be strengthened and
become more active if their sufferings are eased, for these
sufferings increase the state of weakness and physical exhaustion,
check the ardor of soul and sap the moral powers instead of
sustaining them. On the other hand, the suppression of pain
removes any tension in body and mind, renders prayer easy, and
makes possible a more generous gift of self. If some dying persons
accept their suffering as a means of expiation and a source of
merits in order to go forward in the love of God and in
abandonment to His will, do not force anesthetics on them. They
should rather be helped to follow their own way. Where the
situation is entirely different, it would be inadvisable to
suggest to dying persons the ascetical considerations set out
above, and it is to be remembered that instead of assisting
towards expiation and merit, suffering can also furnish occasion
for new faults.
Let Us add a few words on the suppression of consciousness in
the dying in the circumstance where it is not suggested by the
pain. Since Our Lord willed to submit to death fully conscious,
the Christian wishes to imitate Him in that also. In addition, the
Church gives to priests and to the faithful, an Ordo
Commendationis Animae, a collection of prayers which should
help the dying to leave this world and to enter into eternity. But
if those prayers keep their value and meaning even when they are
spoken beside a sick person who is unconscious, to one who is able
to take part in them they ordinarily bring light, consolation and
strength. And so the Church lets it be understood that the sick
person should not, without serious reason, be deprived of
consciousness. When this state is produced by natural causes, men
must accept it; but it is not for them to bring it about unless
they have serious motives for so doing. There is, in addition, the
desire of the persons concerned when they have the faith. They
wish to have the presence of their kindred, of a friend, of a
priest, to help them to die well. They wish to preserve the
possibility of making their final arrangements, of saying a last
prayer, a last word to those around them. To disappoint them in
this is contrary to Christian, nay, to ordinary human sentiment.
The use of anesthetics at the approach of death with the sole
purpose of depriving the sick person of consciousness at the end,
would not be a notable gain in the art of modern healing, but a
practice truly to be regretted.
Your question was proposed rather on the supposition that a
serious medical reason existed (e.g., violent pains,
pathological states of depression and of agony). The dying person
cannot allow, still less ask the doctor to make him unconscious if
he thereby renders himself incapable of fulfilling some serious
moral duties, for example, the settling of important business, the
making of his will, going to confession. We have already said that
the intention of gaining greater merits, taken by itself, is not
an argument sufficient to make the use of drugs unlawful. To judge
of this lawfulness, the question must also be asked whether the
state of insensibility will be relatively short (during the night
or for a few hours) or prolonged (with or without interruption);
one must also consider whether the use of the higher faculties
will return at certain moments for a few minutes at least or for
several hours —and enable the dying person to do what his duty
imposes on him (e.g., to make his peace with God). In
addition, a conscientious doctor, even if he is not a Christian,
will not yield to the urgings of those who, contrary to the will
of the dying person, would wish to make him lose his clarity of
mind in order to prevent him taking certain decisions.
When, in spite of obligations still binding on him, the dying
man asks for the state of insensibility for which there exist
serious reasons, a conscientious doctor will not countenance it,
especially if he is a Christian, without having invited the
patient, either personally or, better still, through some others,
first to carry out his obligations. If the sick man refuses
obstinately, and persists in asking to be made unconscious, the
doctor can consent to it without rendering himself guilty of
formal co-operation in the sin committed. That sin does not really
depend on the fact of unconsciousness, but on the immoral will of
the patient; whether or not he obtains the relief from pain, his
behavior will be the same: he will not carry out his obligation.
Granted that the possibility of repentance is not excluded, there
is yet no serious probability of it; and who knows even that he
will not be hardened in evil?
But if the dying man has fulfilled all his duties and received
the Last Sacrament, if medical reasons clearly suggest the use of
anesthetics, if, in determining the dose, the permitted amount is
not exceeded, if the intensity and duration of this treatment is
carefully reckoned and the patient consents to it, then there is
no objection the use of anesthetics is morally permissible.
The Case of the Sick Who Are Inoperable and Incurable
Would it be necessary to give up its use if the actual effect
of the drug was to shorten the span of life? First, all forms of
direct euthanasia, i.e. the administration of a drug in order to
produce or hasten death, is unlawful because, in that case, a
claim is being made to dispose directly of life. It is one of the
fundamental principles of natural and Christian morality that man
is not the master and owner, but has only the use, of his body and
life. One is putting forward a claim to a right or direct control
every time one wills the shortening of life as an end or as a
means. In the hypothesis which you are considering, there is
question only of ridding the patient of unbearable pains, for
example, in a case of inoperable cancer or of incurable diseases.
If there exists no direct causal link [and usually there
is–because morphine causes respiratory suppression and subsequent
pulmonary infection —Ed.], either through the will of
interested parties or by the nature of things, between the induced
unconsciousness and the shortening of life —as would be the case
if the suppression of the pain could be obtained only by the
shortening of life; and if, on the other hand, the actual
administration of drugs brings about two distinct effects, the one
the relief of pain, the other the shortening of life, the action
is lawful. It is necessary, however, to observe whether there is,
between these two effects, a reasonable proportion, and if the
advantages of the one compensate for the disadvantages of the
other. It is important also to ask oneself if the present state of
science does not allow the same result to be obtained by other
means. Finally, in the use of the drug, one should not go beyond
the limits which are actually necessary.
Conclusion and Answer to the Third Question
To sum up, you ask Us: "Is the removal of pain and
consciousness by means of drugs (when medical reasons suggest it)
permitted by religion and morality to both doctor and patient
(even at the approach of death, and if one foresees that the use
of drugs will shorten life)?" One must answer: "Yes,
provided that no other means exist, and if, in the given
circumstances, that action does not prevent the carrying out of
other moral and religious duties."
As We have already explained, the ideal of Christian heroism
does not require, except in a general way, the refusal of a state
of insensibility, which is justified on other grounds, not even at
the approach of death; all depends on the particular
circumstances. The most perfect and most heroic decision can be
present as fully in acceptance as in refusal.
Final Exhortation
We venture to hope that these considerations on the technique
of pain prevention, looked at from a moral and religious point of
view, will help you to discharge your professional duties with an
even keener sense of your responsibilities. You desire to remain
completely faithful to the demands of your Christian faith and to
abide by it in all your activity. But far from thinking of these
demands as restrictions or as shackles on your liberty and
initiative, regard them rather as an invitation to a life
immeasurably higher and more excellent, which can be won only by
effort and renunciation; for the fullness and joy of that life are
already a matter of experience here below for any one who knows
how to enter into communion with the Person of Christ living in
His Church, quickening it with His spirit, diffusing through all
His members His love as the Redeemer Who alone will finally
triumph over suffering and death.
To the end that Our Lord may impart to you His gifts in full
measure, We earnestly pray to Him for you, for your families and
fellow-workers, and with all Our heart, We grant to you Our
fatherly Apostolic Blessing.
FOOTNOTES
-
Discorsi e Radiomessaggi
, Vol. XVII,
pp.465ff.
-
Gen. 2:16.
-
Ibid., p.478.
-
Cf. Gen. 1:28.
-
Mt. 27:24.
-
Jn. 18:11.
-
Mt. 26:38-39; Lk. 22:42-44.
-
Lk. 12:50.
-
Discorsi e Radiomessaggi, Vol. 15, p.73.
-
Summa Theologica, I, Q.84, A.8.
-
Discorsi e Radiomessaggi, Vol. XVII,
p.467.
-
Mt. 5:48.
-
I Thes. 4:3.
Sidebar:
A health profession which faces increasing challenges to adhere
to Catholic moral and religious compunctions is the pharmaceutical
field. Since the landmark analyses of the pharmaceutical industry
in 1989 (Pharmaceutical Companies: The New Abortionists)
and 1994 (Infant Homicides Through Contraceptives), the
public has witnessed the proliferation of chemical and mechanical
abortifacients within the profession which boasts that it is the
"most trusted."
Fewer and fewer opportunities to practice a "life-saving"
profession present themselves as larger and larger retail chains
and hospital centers swallow up what is left of small, independent
practitioners. With that decimation comes the attitude for less
and less "toleration" for those who profess the Faith through the
corporal and cognitive works of their training.
We see more and more retail and institutional pharmacists
either reprimanded or dismissed for refusing to dispense
contraceptives / abortifacients (many times they are one and the
same) or refusing to refer women where such poisons may be had.
Certainly all is not lost, but the masonic-minded masters continue
to tighten the screws and squeeze those brave souls who adhere to
and practice the Catholic Faith in their profession. There are
pockets of opportunities for those who seek to practice their
profession of work and the Faith, but they must be pursued or
initiated by pharmacists who wish to maintain their moral
scruples.
For more information contact the author at: Bogomir Kuhar,
PharmD, Pharmacists For Life International, PO Box 1281, Powell,
OH 43065-1281 614-881-5520.
Dr. Bruno Haid, head of the Anesthesiology Department at the
University of Innsbruck’s surgery clinic, has submitted to Us
three questions of medical morality concerning what is called
resuscitation. We are pleased, Gentlemen, to respond to his
request, which manifests the keen consciousness you have of your
professional duties, and the desire to resolve the delicate
problems which you face in the light of the principles of the
Gospel.
According to the presentation of Dr. Haid, modern
anesthesiology is not limited to problems of analgesia and
anesthesia strictly speaking, but includes resuscitation as well.
In medicine, and especially in anesthesiology, this word
designates the techniques capable of remedying to certain
life-threatening incidents, especially asphyxias which, formerly,
when modern technology was not available, would lead in just a few
minutes to heart failure and death. The task of the
anesthesiologist thus extends to acute respiratory difficulties
caused by strangulation or occasioned by open thoracopulmonary
wounds. He intervenes to prevent asphyxia due to the internal
obstruction of the respiratory passages caused by stomach
ailments, or by drowning; to remedy total or partial respiratory
paralysis in case of grave tetanus, infantile paralysis, poisoning
by gas, hypnotics, or drunkenness, or even in cases of respiratory
paralysis provoked by serious cranial traumas.
When a doctor practices resuscitation and the treatment of
persons with head injuries, and sometimes persons undergoing brain
surgery or those who have suffered cervical traumas caused by
anoxia and remain plunged in a deep coma, he often is faced with
questions which pertain to medical morals and which call upon the
principles of natural philosophy more so than those of analgesia.
Thus it happens that, in cases like the accidents and illnesses
listed above in which the treatment offers sufficient hope of
success, the anesthesiologist can ameliorate the general condition
of patients suffering from serious brain lesions, whose case
initially appeared hopeless: he can re-establish respiration,
either by manual intervention or with the help of special
equipment, free the respiratory passages and provide for feeding
the patient. Thanks to this therapy, and especially by the
administration of oxygen by means of artificial respiration, the
failing circulation resumes and the patient’s condition improves,
often very quickly, so much so that the anesthesiologist, or any
other doctor who, relying upon his own experience, would have
given up, continues to entertain a slight hope of seeing
spontaneous breathing return. Usually the family considers this
improvement as an astonishing result, for which it is grateful to
the doctor.
If the damage to the brain is so serious that it is probable,
and even practically certain, that the patient will not survive,
the anesthesiologist begins to ask himself the anguishing question
of the worth and meaning of the attempts to resuscitate the
patient. To gain time and to make with greater certitude the final
decisions, he immediately resorts to artificial respiration,
alimentation, and the cleaning of respiratory passages. But then
he can find himself placed in a delicate position if the family
considers his efforts as inconvenient and comes to oppose them.
Most of the time, this happens, not at the beginning of the
attempts at resuscitation, but when the patient’s condition, after
a slight initial improvement, does not progress and when it
becomes clear that the only thing keeping him alive is artificial
respiration. It is at this point that the doctor wonders if he
must, or if he can, continue the attempt at resuscitation, even
though the soul may have already left the body.
The solution to this problem, already difficult in itself,
becomes even more so when the family —perhaps even a Catholic
family —compels the physician in charge to remove the artificial
respiration apparatus in order to allow the patient, already
virtually dead, to go in peace. Thence flows a fundamental
question from the point of view of religion and of the philosophy
of nature: According to the Catholic faith, when does death take
place in patients on whom modern resuscitation techniques are
used? Is Extreme Unction valid at least as long as cardiac
activity can be observed, even if all vital functions properly
so-called have ceased, and if life depends entirely upon the use
of artificial respiration?
The problems raised by the modern practice of resuscitation can
be formulated in three questions:
-
First, has one the right, or even the duty, to use modern
artificial respiration apparatus in every case, even in those
which, in the judgment of the doctor, are considered as
completely hopeless?
-
Secondly, has one the right or the obligation to remove the
artificial respiration apparatus when, after several days, the
state of deep coma does not change, while, if it were removed,
circulation would cease in a few minutes? What should one do in
the case where the family of the patient who has received the
last sacraments, urges the doctor to remove the apparatus? Is
Extreme Unction administered at this stage still valid?
-
Thirdly, should a patient plunged in a coma because of
"central paralysis," but whose life —that is to say, whose
circulatory system —still functions thanks to artificial
respiration, and in whom no signs of improvement have been seen
for several days, be considered as dead de facto, or even
de jure? In order to declare him dead, is it not
necessary for the circulatory system to cease despite the use of
artificial respiration?
We shall reply to each of these questions, but before doing so,
We should like to set forth the principles which will enable Us to
formulate the reply.
Natural reason and Christian morality say that man (and whoever
is responsible for taking care of his brother) has the right and
the duty, in case of grave illness, to take the measures necessary
to conserve life and health. This duty, which he has towards
himself, to God, and even to the human community, and most often
towards specific persons, flows from well-ordered charity, from
submission to the Creator, from social justice and even from
strict justice, as well as from filial piety. But usually the
obligation is limited to the use of ordinary means (according to
the circumstances of person, place, era, and culture), that is to
say, means which impose no extraordinary burden on either oneself
or another. A more severe obligation would be too heavy for most
men, and would render the acquisition of more important higher
goods too difficult. Life, health, all temporal activity, are,
after all, subordinate to spiritual ends. Moreover, it is not
forbidden to do more than the strictly necessary to conserve life
and health, on the condition that higher duties are not neglected.
As for administering the sacraments to a person in a coma, the
answer flows from the doctrine and the practice of the Church,
which, for its part, follows the Lord’s will as a rule of action.
The sacraments are destined, by virtue of divine institution, for
men in this world, during the course of their terrestrial life,
and, with the exception of baptism itself, suppose that the ones
who receive them have been baptized. One who is not a man, one who
is not yet a man or who is no longer, cannot receive the
sacraments. Also, if someone manifests his refusal, the sacraments
cannot be administered against his will. God forces no one to
receive sacramental grace. If it is not known whether someone
fulfills the conditions required for valid reception of a
sacrament, the attempt must be made to remove the doubt. In case
of inability to do so, the sacrament can be conditionally
conferred, at least tacitly (with the clause "si capax est,"
which is broader). The sacraments were instituted by Christ for
men in order to save their souls; thus, in case of extreme
necessity, the Church tries extreme solutions in order to
communicate to a man grace and sacramental aid.
The questions about the fact of death, and about its
recognition, whether by the fact itself (de facto), or by
legal criteria [de son authenticité juridique] (de jure),
have by their consequences, even in the domain of morals and
religion, a still broader scope. What We have just said about the
essential suppositions for the valid reception of a sacrament has
shown it; but the importance of the matter also extends to
questions concerning inheritance, marriage and matrimonial cases,
to questions of benefices (e.g., the vacancy of a benefice)
and to many other questions pertaining to private and public life.
It is incumbent upon the doctor, and especially the
anesthesiologist, to give a clear and precise definition of
"death" and of "the moment of death" of a patient who dies in a
state of coma. In order to do this, one could begin by the usual
concept of the complete and definitive separation of the soul from
the body; but in practice, one must take into account the
impreciseness of terms like "body" and "separation." One can leave
aside the possibility of a man being buried alive, because the
removal of the respiratory apparatus brings on the cessation of
circulation after a few minutes, and then death.
In case of insoluble doubt, one can have recourse to
presumptions of right and of fact. In general, one will stop at
that of the permanence of life, because it involves a matter of a
fundamental right received from the Creator, and it is necessary
to prove with certitude that it has been lost.
We come to the solution of the particular questions.
1) Has the anesthesiologist the right, or even the duty, in
every case of deep coma —even those which are utterly hopeless in
the judgment of the competent physician —to use modern artificial
respiration technology, even against the will of the family?
In ordinary cases, it is granted that the anesthesiologist has
the right to act thusly, but he does not have the obligation,
unless it is the only means to fulfill another incumbent moral
duty. The rights and duties of the doctor are correlative to those
of the patient. In truth, the doctor has no rights that are
separate from or independent of the patient; in general, he cannot
act unless the patient authorizes him to, explicitly or implicitly
(directly or indirectly). The technology of resuscitation, which
is here in question, contains nothing that is in itself immoral;
thus the patient, if he were capable of making the decision
personally, could licitly utilize it, and, consequently, give
authorization to the physician. Moreover, as these forms of
treatment go beyond the ordinary means, which it is obligatory to
use, it cannot be maintained that there is an obligation to use
them, and, consequently, to authorize the physician.
The rights and duties of the family, in general, are dependent
upon the presumed will of the unconscious patient, if he is a
major and "sui juris." As for the family’s own duty
independent of the patient, it usually only obliges them to use
ordinary means. Consequently, if it seems that the attempt at
resuscitation in reality constitutes for the family such a burden
that one cannot in conscience impose it upon them, the family can
licitly insist that the doctor cease his attempts, and the doctor
can licitly obey. In this case there is no direct disposition
taken against the life of the patient, nor euthanasia, which would
never be licit; even when it brings about the failure of the
circulatory system, the interruption of attempts at resuscitation
is never more than indirectly a cause of the cessation of life,
and it is necessary to apply in this case the principle of double
effect and that of "voluntarium in causa."
2) Thus have We already answered the essential points of
the second question: "Can the physician remove the respiratory
apparatus before the definitive cessation of the circulatory
system occurs? Can he do so at least once the patient has already
received Extreme Unction? Is this sacrament valid when
administered at the moment when circulation ceases, or even
afterwards?"
It is necessary to reply in the affirmative to the first part
of this question, as We have already explained. If the sacrament
of Extreme Unction has not yet been administered, one must try to
prolong respiration until it has been. As for knowing if Extreme
Unction is valid at the moment of the definitive cessation of
circulation, or even afterwards, it is impossible to answer by
"yes" or "no." If this definitive cessation signified, in the
opinion of the doctors, the certain separation of soul and body,
even if certain organs continued to function, Extreme Unction
would certainly be invalid, for the one receiving it would
certainly no longer be a man. But that is the one indispensable
condition for the reception of the sacraments. If, on the
contrary, the physicians judge that the separation of body and
soul is doubtful and that this doubt cannot be resolved, the
validity of the Extreme Unction is also doubtful. But applying its
usual rules: "The sacraments are for men" and "In cases
of extreme necessity, extreme measures are tried," the Church
allows the administration of the sacrament, conditionally,
nonetheless, out of respect for the sacramental sign.
3) "When the circulatory system and the life of a
patient in a deep coma caused by central paralysis are only
prolonged by artificial respiration, and without any sign of
improvement occurring for several days, at what point does the
Catholic Church consider this patient as "dead," or is it
necessary, according to natural laws, to declare death
(question de facto and de jure)?"
(In other words, has death occurred after the serious brain
trauma which caused the deep coma and central respiratory
paralysis, the immediate fatal consequences of which have
nonetheless been postponed by means of artificial respiration? Or
does death occur, according to the current opinion of the doctors,
only at the moment of the definitive cessation of the circulatory
system, in spite of the prolonged utilization of artificial
respiration?)
Regarding the determination of the fact in particular cases,
the answer cannot be deduced from any religious or moral principle
and, from this perspective, does not pertain to the competence of
the Church. While waiting, she will remain open. But
considerations of a general nature allow one to think that human
life continues as long as the vital functions —as distinguished
from the simple life of organs —continue to be manifest
spontaneously or even with the aid of artificial assistance. A
good number of these cases fall in the domain of unresolvable
doubt, and should be treated according to the presumptions of
right and of fact of which We have spoken.
May these explanations guide and enlighten you, when you
attempt to resolve the delicate questions that occur in the
practice of your profession. As a token of the divine favors which
We implore for you and all those who are dear to you, We
wholeheartedly grant you our Apostolic blessing.