Perhaps when this article is published, the war against
Iraq may be over. Or God forbid it may have just sparked off a wider
conflict. Whatever the case, these few lines will not attempt to deal with
the geopolitical or military aspects of the Iraqi war, which are beyond the
author’s expertise, but will only examine its moral justification.
As it has been said in a former article,1 to
state the conditions in which a just war is morally licit is an ethical
judgment, whereas to decide that, here and now, a war should be fought is a
judgment of political prudence. In other words, to know the
conditions in which a just war may be fought is one thing; to establish
whether those conditions are or are not realized in a particular case is a
different and far more difficult matter. We must be guided to concrete
decisions by a body of principles of justice, previous to any conflict,
grounded in the Eternal Reason of God; but our prudential judgment depends
on the knowledge of all the relevant facts in the concrete case. Moreover,
we must be acutely aware of the danger of error through the manipulation of
propaganda and the easy slogans of sentimental patriotism.
Many have spoken, as a justification for the war against
Iraq, of "pre-emptive strikes" and of "preventive war." Upon reflection, it
would seem that such moral
that it is the personal opinion of the author of this
article that, on the basis of the facts that are of public knowledge, the
conditions for a "just war" do not seem to have been fulfilled in the
present war.2
As difficult as it seems for some people to understand
it, to be against this war does not mean to be against the American troops,
or to be for Saddam Hussein, or to hate America.
People of good will may differ on how to apply the just
war norms in particular cases. Nevertheless, there is always a serious
obligation for all…to justify their own conclusions as measured against the
moral norms of Catholic teaching.3
"Just Cause" For War
The Catholic "just-war theory" acknowledges the right of
nations to self-defense: war is licit when there is a question of defending
the common good against an unjust aggression.4 This is simply an
application of the natural law just as it is obvious that every man has the
right to preserve his own existence, so too does the state have the natural
right to employ force in legitimate defense against a threat to its very
existence that is real, immediate and grave.
But the term "defense" has been understood by Catholic
theologians in a wider sense. Hence, military force may be rightfully
employed either as self-defense against an unjust attack; or for the
restoration or recuperation of what was unjustly taken; or for the
punishment of unjust aggressors.5
Among private individuals, the time for defense is
limited to the time of the unjust aggression. However, for the public
authority, not only defense against an actual attack, but also retaliation
against a past aggression may be still legitimately called a matter of
defense because the injury continues being inflicted (and so violence is
still being exercised) throughout the entire time that the aggressor refuses
to return what he has taken or to amend the violation he has made. The use
of force to recover what was lost thereby becomes legitimate, if force is
the only means to do so.
The public authority also has the right, and sometimes
even the duty, to punish evildoers to take "vengeance." As the goal of war
is the restoration of peace that is, of the just order justice demands more
than simply rendering the aggressor incapable of doing further damage and
despoiling him of what he had unjustly taken. Justice requires that the
criminal also make satisfaction for his evildoing, and this is the object of
vengeance. As long as such satisfaction has not been made, it can be said
that the order of justice continues to be violated, that an injury continues
to be inflicted against which a nation can defend itself.
This is not "getting even," but an act of vindictive
justice from which will result manifold benefits. The culpable party makes
amends for his crime, or he is at least kept from doing further damage. The
authority maintains public order by repressing evils as they appear. It is a
safeguard for future justice since others will be deterred from similar
crimes by fear of similar retribution. And it upholds the honor of God, the
Just Judge, whom men are called to imitate.
"Pre-emptive Strike"
Thus the first use of force in any given conflict is
always morally suspect, as it appears to be aggression. The second use, as
it is reaction to the attack, is not so suspect, in principle, and is
considered purely defensive. But in certain complex circumstances the first
use of force may be in reality defensive, although it cannot be easily
perceived as such. It is in these cases that the terms "pre-emptive strike"
and "preventive war" are likely to be used. They must be clearly defined, if
we are to understand their moral status. Therefore, let it be understood
that the "use of pre-emptive force" (or a "pre-emptive strike")
means that we attack our adversary, although he has not yet actually
attacked us.
Moral Argument
Such a course of action may be allowed only when it
constitutes self-defense in the wider sense stated above. That is, it
is morally permissible only when there is, on the part of the adversary, a manifest intent to injure, a degree of active preparation
that makes that intent a positive danger, and a general situation in
which waiting or doing anything other than fighting greatly magnifies the
risk.6
If the "pre-emptive" force is to be used either as a
means of obtaining satisfaction for damage previously inflicted or to punish
evildoers, it has to be proven beyond any reasonable doubt (because of the
evils that war will unleash upon him) that it is defensive that is, that the
adversary is the cause of such damage, or that he has efficaciously
cooperated in inflicting it.
It is an acknowledged legal principle that the burden of
proof rests on him who affirms or accuses. In our case, the burden of proof
either that there is such "manifest intent," or that the threat of the
adversary’s attack is impending, "overwhelming, and leaving no choice of
means and no moment for deliberation,"7 or that the adversary is
the cause of the damage inflicted, rests on the government that decides to
launch the pre-emptive strike.
It may be argued that, given the complexities of the
contemporary international situation, the dangers of "asymmetrical warfare"
and the existence of clandestine networks of terrorism, only the public
authorities are "close to the facts of the case and…privy to highly
restricted intelligence,"8 and, therefore, they are not obliged
to disclose their evidence when doing so may endanger their sources or
jeopardize the outcome of the war. Catholic moral doctrine has always made
allowances for such a case, stating that the common citizen must, a
priori, trust his government and presume the justice of the war.9
But that presumption, while justifiable for the
individual citizen, is not appropriate for the international community.
Because of today’s increased solidarity and mutual interaction of nations,
military conflicts have the capacity to expand and to compromise severely
the international order. In consequence, today’s threshold of what
constitutes the "common good" must be raised to include, in certain
extraordinary cases, the higher common good of that international order.
It is only just, therefore, for the international
community before committing itself or giving its sanction to a proposed
military action to demand not only assurances but also proofs of a clear
case for a war that, one way or another, has the potential to endanger their
own common good, for whose protection they are responsible before God and
their own peoples, and the international common good in whose pursuit all
must collaborate.
During the Cuban missile crisis of 1962, the US
Ambassador to the United Nations, Adlai Stevenson, justified the American
readiness to use military force to confront the specific threats from Russia
by presenting photos that unquestionably showed the Russian missile array in
Cuba. For the war against Iraq, the present US Administration has not
offered such convincing proof to the international community. Consequently,
the UN Security Council has remained unconvinced, and unwilling to endorse
the American military action against Iraq.
It may be argued that the nation-members of the Security
Council have their own political agendas and that perhaps they would have
denied such endorsement even with undeniable proof of Iraq’s threat.
Perhaps, but the fact remains that a demand of justice has not been
satisfied.
"Preventive War"
The notion of "preventive war" has been recently
presented to the Catholic world by Michael Novak10 in a lecture
given in Rome at the invitation of the US Ambassador to the Holy See, James
Nicholson.
This address, although it has drawn impassioned protests
from influential American Catholics,11 failed nevertheless to
make a coherent argument in favor of the war. It starts by asserting that
"preventive war" is not a new theory, but an application of the Catholic
just-war doctrine. In the same paragraph, though, it affirms that the
present "preventive war" is simply a follow-up of previous UN sanctions,
bringing to a close the 1991 Gulf Warthen, one does not see the need to talk
of it as "preventive." A few sentences later, the war is nonetheless
"preventive" because it removes the odds that, one day, terrorists and
Saddam Hussein may collaborate to attack America.
As Novak in his vagueness does not offer a definition of
it, we are entitled to extrapolate from his text a definition of "preventive
war" as the unilateral attack that neutralizes what is, at present, only
the mere possibility of a future attack of a potential adversary. In
other words, military force is inflicted upon a country to prevent a threat
that such country may or may not pose in the future, but which we fear it
may. Thus, the rationale for war is not the adversary’s actual
threat, but our own assessment of his possible future
intentions. In other words, the debatable conclusions of our own
guesswork are the motive for war.
As we have said, a case may be made in support of the
moral permissibility of the use of "pre-emptive force," but "preventive
war" is indefensible on moral grounds.
Many supporters of the war have spoken, indistinctly, of
"pre-emptive strikes" and of "preventive war." On a moral basis, attention
must be called to the fact that precisely because the notion of pre-emptive
strike may have some moral permissibility in certain circumstances, while
the preventive war has no justification at all the moral discourse that ties
both notions together and uses them as equivalent is, to say the least,
confusing.
To portray a "preventive war" merely as a "pre-emptive
strike" is if done deliberately no more than a perverse example of Orwellian
"newspeak.
Moral Argument
Why is this portrayal perverse? —Because war is morally
permissible only as a means of self-defense. Even the "anticipatory
self-defense" or "pre-emptive strike "is a morally permissible action
because it is, after all, defense of self against an unjust aggression
already underway. In such a case, and at least morally speaking, the attack
upon us has started. There are four reasons why "preventive war" is immoral:
1. It is not defense. In a "preventive war,"
on the other hand, as we have defined it, there is no "defense" in the sense
that there is no actual attack underway to defend oneself against. Or,
rather, the term "underway" has been so expanded to include also our own
assessment of the mere possibility of, or potentiality for, a future attack
that is, it is "underway" when we say so.
In a "preventive war" so defined, the dubious
conclusions of our conjectures about the adversary’s possible but
unproven intentions are taken as certainty of his intent to injure
us. Once such spurious "certainty" has taken the place of real proof, it is
argued (wrongfully and unlawfully) that the attack is "underway," and one
slithers easily (but still wrongfully and unlawfully) into the moral
argument of "self-defense."
2. Certainty is required. To act morally, one
must have moral certainty of the justice of the war. "Moral" certainty is
that which, although as it refers to contingent facts it cannot exclude all
possibility of error, nonetheless leaves no reasonable and prudent doubt
about the rectitude of the decision to be taken.
Now, certainty is the effect of evidence. As the damage
to be inflicted by a war upon the adversary is real, absolutely certain, and
much of it irreparable, the decision to wage war must be based upon
proportional, morally certain reasons. Presumption in the absence of
evidence is not sufficient to justify morally an action with such dreadful
consequences.
3. Modern risks do not justify it. It is
undeniable, as Novak and George Weigel point out, that the development of
new technologies, the increased threat of global terrorism and the
consequent new concept of asymmetrical warfare12 have changed the
face of war in the modern world. The normal criteria to be looked for in the
assessment of a just-war situation may not be present no conventional
military movements (as Weigel puts it, no more question "of waiting for
the redcoats to crest the hill at dawn"), no visible signs of imminent
attack, no authority of a hostile state who assumes responsibility for the
attack.13
Even so, the mere ability of a country, even an
unfriendly one, to launch a war is not sufficient cause for a just war.14
The just war is a defensive one. The notion of "defense" may be construed so
as to cover a wide array of concrete situations, but it is always reaction
to an actual attack or to the adversary’s "manifest intent" to injure.
However reasonable may be the fears for the safety of
one’s country, however much the risks may have increased in modern times,
however tactically expedient and, in the long run, safer it may be to
neutralize such odds, the moral principle remains the same: "non faciamus
mala ut veniant bona," it is not permissible to inflict an evil to
obtain a good result. A government has certainly the duty to protect its
citizens, but it also has the higher obligation of submitting to the moral
law (which is, in the end, nothing else than the Law of God).
4. It is aggression. Whatever terms we choose
to designate such action,
the "preventive war" is a war of aggression,
unjustifiable on moral grounds and according to international law. To
intervene it is required to have proofs...15
In practice, supporters of the present war have expanded
the traditional notion of "anticipatory self-defense" to the point where it
includes the first use of force, on the basis of its presumption of the
hostile intentions of the adversary. Therefore, it certainly seems
aggression, and, thus, unjust.
Might Is Right?
Political analysts speak of a new American strategy,
which seems to be focused on the preservation of the unipolarity16
achieved with the end of the Cold War. In practice, it would mean that
America is ready to intervene anywhere, any time, to neutralize any serious
threat to its global dominance. If this is true, "we may have become the
very thing we hated about Communism… an ideology willing to invade and
control countries to impose its will." 17 Non-aligned states,
by the mere fact of their non-alignment, will be deemed to pose a threat.
The mere possession of weapons of mass destruction by an unfriendly
government, even without the violation of any existing international law,
will be considered as a threat that has to be counteracted.18
"America has extended [this policy] to global dimensions, reserving
for itself the authority to determine when sovereignty has been forfeited,
and doing so on an anticipatory basis." 19
Many see in the present war against Iraq the "first
and paradigmatic application" of this new and fateful strategy.20
Yet Saddam Hussein is not the only dangerous dictator in
the world. There are several other countries that possess and unscrupulously
market weapons of mass destruction. There are other nations in the "axis of
evil," and there are some that are not even mentioned, but should be
enrolled there. North Korea has weapons of mass destruction, even nuclear
ones, and in the past has shown no qualms about selling them; it has
moreover refused UN supervision and actually threatened America. Pakistan
and Saudi Arabia are considered by political analysts and intelligence
services as very likely to have had a hand in the September 11 attacks.21
The disturbing question remains unanswered: why Iraq? The answer proposed by
some of those political analysts, who make a remarkably credible case for
it,22 is still more disturbing.
May the Lord God of Armies, Dominus Deus Sabaoth,
grant to us and to those in authority over us light for our intelligences
and strong and serene hearts to walk in righteousness in His sight.